Dissidents Philosophy Forum
Would you like to react to this message? Create an account in a few clicks or log in to continue.

Dissidents Philosophy Forum

Internet Philosophical Community
 
HomeLatest imagesSearchRegisterLog in

 

 Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.

Go down 
2 posters
AuthorMessage
The Fool
Administrator
The Fool


Male
Number of posts : 368
Age : 37
Location : United States Midwest
Registration date : 2008-12-12

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeSun Jan 18, 2009 1:01 pm

For the most part justice and law only benefits those with power when it is not acting as public service of revenge or retribution.

What did Thrasymachus have to say about the subject from Plato's Republic?


Quote :
What I say is that 'just' or 'right' means nothing but what is in the interest of the stronger party.


Quote :
Listen—I say that justice is nothing other than the advantage of the stronger.

Quote :
Thus, Socrates, injustice on a sufficiently large scale is a stronger, freer, and a more masterful thing than justice, and, as I said in the beginning, it is the advantage of the stronger that is the just, while the unjust is what profits man's self and is for his advantage."

Quote :
'To do injustice is said to be a good; to suffer injustice an evil. As the evil is discovered by experience to be greater than the good, the sufferers, who cannot also be doers, make a compact that they will have neither, and this compact or mean is called justice, but is really the impossibility of doing injustice. No one would observe such a compact if he were not obliged. Let us suppose that the just and unjust have two rings, like that of Gyges in the well-known story, which make them invisible, and then no difference will appear in them, for every one will do evil if he can. And he who abstains will be regarded by the world as a fool for his pains. Men may praise him in public out of fear for themselves, but they will laugh at him in their hearts


Quote :
'And now let us frame an ideal of the just and unjust. Imagine the unjust man to be master of his craft, seldom making mistakes and easily correcting them; having gifts of money, speech, strength--the greatest villain bearing the highest character: and at his side let us place the just in his nobleness and simplicity--being, not seeming--without name or reward-- clothed in his justice only--the best of men who is thought to be the worst, and let him die as he has lived. I might add (but I would rather put the rest into the mouth of the panegyrists of injustice--they will tell you) that the just man will be scourged, racked, bound, will have his eyes put out, and will at last be crucified (literally impaled)--and all this because he ought to have preferred seeming to being. How different is the case of the unjust who clings to appearance as the true reality! His high character makes him a ruler; he can marry where he likes, trade where he likes, help his friends and hurt his enemies; having got rich by dishonesty he can worship the gods better, and will therefore be more loved by them than the just.


Last edited by The Fool on Sun Jan 25, 2009 12:55 pm; edited 4 times in total
Back to top Go down
https://dissidentsphilosophy.forumotion.com
Unreasonable
Animated Voice
Animated Voice
Unreasonable


Male
Number of posts : 728
Age : 41
Location : Purgatory
Registration date : 2008-12-13

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeMon Jan 19, 2009 11:44 am

This seems rather incorrect Fool.

It is more accurate to say that Injustice only benefits those who already-hold power. Justice is something more.
Back to top Go down
The Fool
Administrator
The Fool


Male
Number of posts : 368
Age : 37
Location : United States Midwest
Registration date : 2008-12-12

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeTue Jan 20, 2009 9:21 am

Unreasonable wrote:
This seems rather incorrect Fool.

It is more accurate to say that Injustice only benefits those who already-hold power. Justice is something more.

Of course my post made little to no sense at all in that it was unfortunately incomplete.

( When I was making this thread the computer I was on crashed because of a server malfunction.)

( You shall find the next posts a little more enlightening on the subject.) Twisted Evil

( Please note that which is underlined is of severe importance to our conversation and viewing pleasure.)


Last edited by The Fool on Tue Jan 20, 2009 9:37 am; edited 3 times in total
Back to top Go down
https://dissidentsphilosophy.forumotion.com
The Fool
Administrator
The Fool


Male
Number of posts : 368
Age : 37
Location : United States Midwest
Registration date : 2008-12-12

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeTue Jan 20, 2009 9:23 am

Quote :
In the beginning of Republic II, during a conversation with Socrates and Adeimantus about which individual is deemed happier, the one who is just or the one who is unjust, Glaucon states:

For the extreme of injustice is to seem to be just when one is not. So the perfectly unjust man must be given the most perfect injustice, and nothing must be taken away; he must be allowed to do the greatest injustices while having provided himself with the greatest reputation for justice. And if, he should trip up in anything, he has the power to set himself aright; if any of his unjust deeds should come to light, he is capable both of speaking persuasively and of using force, to the extent that force is needed, since he is courageous and strong and since he has provided for friends and money. (361a-b)(1)

I believe that Glaucon has captured the essence of the Thrasymachean position concerning the best way for the unjust individual to live. The one who pursues the life of injustice must at the same time be courageous and crafty, strong and shrewd, power-driven and persuasive. But most importantly, the unjust individual must be dastardly and deceptive. This deception is captured by Glaucon when he states that the perfectly unjust man must "seem" to be just. Appearances and reputations played a central role in the fifth century b.c.e. Greek polis and so it makes sense that Glaucon would cast light upon the idea of an individual’s pursuit of the unjust life while providing for the "greatest reputation for justice."(2) Such an individual leads a kind of double life and therefore has a double duty to perform in seeming to be just while actually being unjust.

These comments regarding Glaucon’s view of the perfectly unjust individual hint at the purpose of this discussion. This paper has a three-fold task. First, I will show that there are three types of individuals associated with the Thrasymachean view of society: a) the many, i.e., the ruled or those exploited individuals who are just and obey the laws of the society; b) the tyrant or ruler who sets down laws in the society to exploit the many for personal advantage; c) the "stronger" individual (kreitton) or member of the society who detaches from the many and aspires to become the tyrant.

Most commentaries dealing with Thrasymachus’ position give the tyrant and the many central roles in the discussion of justice and injustice.(3) My view draws out the role of the stronger individual in Thrasymachus’ account in order to show the activities associated with the genesis of the tyrant from the society. The stronger individual, in seeking the life of injustice, naturally detaches from the many and aspires to develop into the perfectly unjust tyrant. In the third section of this paper I shall argue that if Thrasymachus’ account of the perfectly unjust life of the tyrant is to be more than a theoretical ideal, then the stronger individual who aspires to become the tyrant would do well to lead a double life of pursuing private injustice while maintaining the public "appearance" of justice. My view conforms to Glaucon’s interpretation noted in the quotation above whereby a double life of justice and injustice is maintained by the tyrant who seeks to maintain power over the society. I want to extend Glaucon’s interpretation to include the stronger individual as well.

In the final section of this paper I will enter into dialogue with those commentators who maintain that Thrasymachus’ position concerning justice and injustice is inconsistent overall. I believe that a solution to the problem of inconsistency in Thrasymachus’ position can be achieved when considering the role of the stronger as a separate type of individual in the society. Thus, I will argue that the standpoint of the stronger, as distinct from the standpoints of the tyrant and the many, has value in that it shows Thrasymachus’ three statements regarding justice to be consistent with one another.

II.

It is clear throughout Republic I, and specifically in his speech at 344a, that Thrasymachus has in mind the tyrant as exemplary of the perfectly unjust individual who "by stealth and force takes away what belongs to others, both what is sacred and profane, private and public, not bit by bit, but all at once." It is also clear, given the three statements Thrasymachus makes about justice as a) being advantageous to the stronger (338c), b) obedience to law (339c) and c) the good of another (343c) that the tyrant sets down laws in the society strictly for the tyrant’s own personal advantage. From the standpoint of the many, the three statements regarding justice are consistent with the idea that what is just is always advantageous to the tyrant. Seen from this standpoint, the very act of obedience to the laws set down in a society involves the many in an exploitative situation. According to Thrasymachus, the tyrant, in seeking a life of perfect injustice, "overreaches" (pleonektein) in exploiting the many. This means that the tyrant always greedily seeks to acquire more than a fair share and as Thrasymachus puts it, "get the better in a big way" (343e).


Last edited by The Fool on Tue Jan 20, 2009 9:38 am; edited 1 time in total
Back to top Go down
https://dissidentsphilosophy.forumotion.com
The Fool
Administrator
The Fool


Male
Number of posts : 368
Age : 37
Location : United States Midwest
Registration date : 2008-12-12

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeTue Jan 20, 2009 9:25 am

Quote :
The tyrant can exploit the many because of the fact that the tyrant is the stronger of the two. At 339c and 343c Thrasymachus concludes that in every political situation the ruling body sets down laws that are to the advantage of the rulers precisely because such a ruling body is stronger than the hoi polloi. As the stronger ruler, the tyrant has the power to punish lawbreakers (338e), take away what belongs to others (344a), kidnap and enslave the many (344b) with the added benefit of being called "happy and blessed" for so doing (344b-c). Thrasymachus makes a connection between the notion of strength and the capacity for leading an unjust life. At 343c justice is defined by Thrasymachus as "really someone else’s good, the advantage of the man who is stronger and rules."(4) Injustice, we are told "is the opposite, and it rules the truly simple and just." So the life of injustice in its essence will be a self-seeking activity and the tyrant, who can pursue this life most perfectly on a grand scale, is in the position to frame social interaction in a way that is wholly self-advantageous. Thus, Thrasymachus can say to Socrates and company:

injustice, when it comes into being on a sufficient scale, is mightier, freer, and more masterful than justice; and, as I have said from the beginning, the just is the advantage of the stronger, and the unjust is what is profitable and advantageous for oneself. (344c)

Thus far I have made explicit the existence of the tyrant as the unjust exploiter and the many as the just exploited in Thrasymachus’ view of the society. But there is another type of individual associated with society who, in a strict sense, is neither the tyrant nor a member of the many—namely, the kreitton. In his long speech that runs from 343b to 344c, Thrasymachus speaks of the tyrant as exemplary of the most perfect injustice. But within the context of this speech, he also mentions those who are only "partially" unjust: temple robbers, kidnappers, housebreakers, defrauders and thieves. (344b) Further, in contrasting concrete examples that distinguish the benefits of the unjust life as distinct from the just life, Thrasymachus states: "the just man everywhere has less than the unjust man." He continues:

First, in contracts, when the just man is a partner of the unjust man, you will always find that at the dissolution of the partnership the just man does not have more than the unjust man, but less. Second, in matters pertaining to the city, when there are taxes, the just man pays more on the basis of equal property, the unjust man less; and where there are distributions, the one makes no profit, the other much. (343d)

Here, Thrasymachus is not speaking specifically of the tyrant in relation to the many. The type of unjust individual Thrasymachus speaks of in this quotation, as well as the housebreaker and thief, are those individuals who realize that to do justice means to place oneself in a weaker exploitative situation. Such individuals exemplify the stronger person who seeks the unjust life of what is "profitable and advantageous for oneself." The stronger resembles the tyrant in seeking the unjust life but lacks the perfection of injustice which "by stealth and force" overpowers the many "all at once."

Thrasymachus is concerned to show that if individuals in the society are in a position to do so, they should strive to do whatever is in their power to achieve the status of the tyrant because he thinks that the one who rules is the strongest, most powerful and consequently happiest individual in the society (344a-b). There is a developmental genesis of the tyrant within the context of society being made explicit by Thrasymachus’ account of the stronger. Thrasymachus’ examples of defrauders, kidnappers and those thieves who violate the commutative and distributive laws of justice confirm this to be the case. Actually, by explicating the role that the stronger plays in Thrasymachus’ social milieu, we get a better understanding of both the just and the unjust individual. Seen in this way, the stronger acts as a kind of midpoint character between the many and the tyrant—between justice and extreme injustice. The stronger is on the way to tyranthood transcending the exploitations of the society as exploiter; however, such exploits fall short of the tyrant who, in the words of Thrasymachus, "does injustice entire" (344c).


Last edited by The Fool on Tue Jan 20, 2009 9:40 am; edited 2 times in total
Back to top Go down
https://dissidentsphilosophy.forumotion.com
The Fool
Administrator
The Fool


Male
Number of posts : 368
Age : 37
Location : United States Midwest
Registration date : 2008-12-12

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeTue Jan 20, 2009 9:28 am

Quote :
III.

It is appropriate that Thrasymachus uses the image of sheep or cows in his speech at 343b to describe the many because there is a sense in which the individuals subject to a tyranny are incapable of overpowering the "sheep/cow-herder" or, like grazing animals, are unaware of what is truly going on around themselves. The question then becomes, "Are the many really so naive as to allow themselves to be exploited by some tyrannical ruler?" Two responses come to mind. The first is "No." People are not so naive as to not know that they are being exploited. They obey the laws and rules because they know full well who has the power and fear the consequences of disobedience. Or, they obey because they think they can placate or appease the tyrant’s self-indulgent pleonexia. Still some, like Socrates himself, know who is in charge and what is really going on, but obey the laws nonetheless on the grounds of a principle or ideal. This response would be consistent with Thrasymachus’s standpoint concerning the ruling power of the tyrant.

The second response to the question of the many's naivete is "Yes." It could be the case that the many are a group of really dense individuals who just cannot see the exploitation. There is another response related to this idea of naivete which considers the possibility that the tyrant in a society sets up laws that appear to be for the advantage of the many, but in reality are for the tyrant’s advantage. This has to do with Glaucon’s statement which I quoted in the first lines of this paper relating to the idea of seeming to be just when one is not. In his article entitled, "In Defense of Thrasymachus" T. Y. Henderson considers a similar alternative when he offers a hypothetical case whereby a "politically ambitious... intelligent and courageous" man named Setarcos is able to elevate himself to the status of the ruler by maintaining a "public facade of honesty and integrity."(5) In public Setarcos professes that the just life is the best life for individuals and is in fact, in the public arena, obedient to the laws of the society. But he secretly leads a private life of immorality whereby he "advances his own fortunes at the expense of others."(6) Eventually, through his private immoral maneuverings, and his public facade of justice, honesty and integrity, he becomes the ruler of the society. And when in power as the ruler, he is able to maintain this public facade "for a long time or even indefinitely, while remaining a thoroughly unjust man."(7)

Henderson asks if it is really possible for an immoral individual to dupe an entire society in such a way. Surely there would be some individuals who would catch on to Setarcos’ plans and realize that in acting justly by following the laws of the society, they would actually be serving the interests of Setarcos. In response to this, Henderson states that "Setarcos would want everyone in the state (except himself who knows better) to act justly, to live just lives, and to believe sincerely that in doing so they were serving their own best interests."(Cool Henderson believes this to be a plausible account that is consistent with Thrasymachean immorality. As Henderson states:

If Setarcos were able to convince everyone in the state that he is a completely just man, that because he is just he is happy, that justice in general is most profitable to man as a way of life, while at the same time being able, covertly, to cheat and steal from the people systematically, then he would conform perfectly to Thrasymachus’ conception of the strong man.(9)

Henderson’s account is valuable for two reasons. First, it shows how the tyrant can remain unjust without being an iron-fisted dictator who, in Thrasymachus’ words, "takes away what belongs to others, both what is sacred and profane, private and public... all at once" (344a). Even the most dense member of the society is going to recognize the villainy of an iron-fisted dictator and will consequently harbor feelings of fear and resentment toward such an approach. Henderson shows us that the tyrant can be cunning, covert and corrupt while appearing to be courteous, caring and concerned. And further, Henderson shows the value of such an approach as it lends itself to happiness on the parts of both the tyrant and the many. The tyrant’s happiness lies in true exploitation; the happiness of the many lies in believing that leading a just life is actually to their advantage.

Secondly, Henderson’s account is valuable because it underscores the point I have been making about the existence of the stronger in the society. Henderson tells us that

the strongest man in the state is most likely to be, or to become the ruler. He rises to the top naturally because he takes advantage of every opportunity to make an unjust profit and to further his own cause at the expense of others. Everyone and every group who deal with him justly are exploited by him for his own profit.(10)


This account of the stronger can be coupled with the idea expressed by Glaucon that the unjust individual must "seem to be just" or the account given by Henderson that, as he rises to the top, the strong man Setarcos maintains a "public facade of honesty and integrity." In this way, the stronger leads a double life of pursuing injustice while seeming to pursue what is just. And in this way, the stronger dupes both the many and the tyrant.

That the stronger dupes both the many and the tyrant can be verified when we look at what Thrasymachus says in the text itself. Thrasymachus has made it clear that the unjust life is to be preferred to the just and that individuals in the society do act and should act so as to dupe their fellow neighbor. On the one hand, the stronger individual is clever enough to exploit the many as in Thrasymachus’s example of the broken contract at 343d. Again, we are told that as a result of such a contractual relationship, the "just man does not have more than the unjust man." But on the other hand, the stronger individual is clever enough to dupe the many along with the tyrant as in the case of the tax evasion mentioned in the same section: "in matters pertaining to the city, when there are taxes, the just man pays more on the basis of equal property, the unjust man less" (343d). This again shows the distinction more explicitly among the types of individuals (i.e., the many, the stronger and the tyrant) that can be found in Thrasymachus’ presentation of the just versus the unjust. And further, the stronger is shown to clearly and consistently conform to Thrasymachus’ description of the unjust individual.


Last edited by The Fool on Tue Jan 20, 2009 9:44 am; edited 1 time in total
Back to top Go down
https://dissidentsphilosophy.forumotion.com
The Fool
Administrator
The Fool


Male
Number of posts : 368
Age : 37
Location : United States Midwest
Registration date : 2008-12-12

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeTue Jan 20, 2009 9:29 am

Quote :
IV.

We are now in a position to address the issue of consistency in Thrasymachus’ position. Commentators concerning Thrasymachus’ position are divided. There are those, like G. F. Hourani, who see Thrasymachus as advocating a legalism.(11) And there are those, like G. B. Kerferd, T. Y. Henderson and Julia Annas who maintain that Thrasymachus holds to an immoralism.(12) Many commentators are in agreement, however, that Thrasymachus position concerning justice and injustice is lacking in self-consistence.(13) The reason commentators see a lack of consistency in Thrasymachus’ position has to do with the fact that Thrasymachus says three distinct things about justice in the course of his conversation with Socrates and company. Justice is at once:

1) "nothing other than the advantage of the stronger" (338c)
2) obeying the laws of the ruler(s) (339b)
3) "really someone else’s good, the advantage of the man who is stronger and rules" (343c)


The inconsistency arises precisely because both the ruled and the ruler must be taken into account when considering justice and injustice. Thrasymachus ultimately reveals that justice is "another's good" and it is this statement that involves him in a logical contradiction and much controversy from Socrates onward. Some commentators, such as Henderson, maintain that these three statements are consistent when seen from the standpoint of the many.(14) Considered from this standpoint, Thrasymachus’ three statements about justice and its opposite are consistent because the "other" that Thrasymachus refers to is the ruling tyrant: justice is obeying the laws set up by the ruler (statement #2 at 339b), and in obeying these laws the many are concerned for the other (statement #3 at 343c), i.e., the tyrant who has set up these laws with the advantage going to the tyrant as the stronger of the two parties (statement #1 at 338c).

From the standpoint of the tyrant, however, the statements regarding justice and injustice are inconsistent. Kerferd and Annas are examples of commentators who have maintained that Thrasymachus’ position is not consistent overall. Despite the inconsistency, they think that Thrasymachus is ultimately advocating an immoralism since justice is defined as "another’s good," i.e., the advantage of the stronger tyrant. From what he says at 343b, Thrasymachus makes it clear that the life of justice as another's good is to be rejected and that the life of injustice is to be accepted; thus, the immoralist position. However, when this definition of justice is applied to the ruled as well as to the ruler, there arises the problem of consistency in the definition itself. Statements 1)-3) hold from the standpoint of the ruled in society. In this sense, the "another’s good" which the ruled promotes in being just or violates in being unjust is precisely that of the ruling tyrant. But the injustice of the second part of the statement implies that the "other" in the first part is not the ruling tyrant, but the ruled many. Herein lies the problem of inconsistency, and, as Annas points out:

The same situation is described as both being just, form the point of view of the subjects who are serving the interests of another, and as unjust, from the point of view of the ruler who is exploiting them in his own interests.(15)

From the standpoint of the ruled, the "another" is the ruler; from the standpoint of the ruler, the "another" is the ruled. So, it is clear that the praising of injustice from the ruler's perspective rests upon a standard of justice that is found to be the case from the ruled's perspective and therefore, the ruler never really escapes the standards of justice and injustice as Thrasymachus would want us to believe.


Annas notes that Thrasymachus starts off with a "muddled" position and, once in dialogue with Socrates, makes his position clearer. The three statements Thrasymachus makes "strictly speaking" conflict with one another in the end. Thrasymachus began by "thinking only of strong and successful rulers"(16) and, because of this, he first defines justice in a way that strictly applied only to their subjects, who by acting justly are serving the interests of their rulers, the stronger, and who are acting in a way that is to the interests not of themselves but of others.(17)

Likewise, Kerferd maintains that if all the statements that Thrasymachus makes regarding justice are to be taken seriously, "then he cannot have an overall consistent account of justice to offer."(18) In light of this overall inconsistency, Kerferd and Annas feel justified in holding that the third statement, i.e., "justice is another's good" is the real Thrasymachean position. Kerferd holds this view because he envisions Thrasymachus as trying to give an account of justice that will take into account the ruler and the ruled in society. According to Kerferd, the ruler is the stronger "other" in the society who lays down laws specifically for the interest of exploiting the ruled. Kerferd continues to state that Thrasymachean justice "always" entails seeking another's interest and therefore must be "scorned" as "something silly." The true ideal is "for everyone to seek his own interest" by leading a life of injustice.(19) To this extent, it would be just for the ruled in a society to obey the laws because these laws are set out for the good of another—namely, the tyrant. Kerferd does not see an inconsistency between the statements "justice is the interest of the stronger" and "justice is another's good" when considered from the standpoint of the ruled. In this case, when the ruled act justly, they do so for the stronger other's benefit who happens to be the ruling tyrant. But justice as obeying the laws is viewed by Kerferd as being inconsistent with justice as another's good or the interest of the stronger because the laws that are laid down by the tyrant for the ruled to follow could be mistakenly laid out and found to actually not be in the interest of the "other," i.e., the ruling tyrant.

Annas and Kerferd's concerns are well noted and justified. The inconsistency might be reconciled if we hold the view that the tyrant remains unjust in the concern for self only if the third statement about justice as being a concern for the other reveals that the other is merely the many. We really cannot maintain that the "other" Thrasymachus speaks of at 343c is the many because this "other" is immediately qualified as "the man who is stronger and rules" or the tyrant. (343c) And again, we see that outside of this limited interpretation of the other as the many, the tyrant would be mitigating against the personal advantage that is sought whenever the tyrant acted unjustly. When taking Thrasymachus’ three statements regarding justice and injustice in their entirety, it seems to follow that if justice is what is advantageous for the tyrant, then injustice, as its opposite, would be disadvantageous for the tyrant. The tyrant, in acting unjustly towards the many, wants the many to act justly towards the tyrant. However, from the standpoint of the tyrant Thrasymachus cannot endorse the injustice he defines.

When all is said and done, it seems apparent that Thrasymachus was not concerned with this inconsistency and that the utter power and strength associated with the notion of injustice became his real concern. That the strength and power associated with injustice became Thrasymachus’ ultimate concern is upheld by Annas and Kerferd,(20) but also verified in the text when Thrasymachus rejects Cleitophon’s suggestion that what Thrasymachus meant by the advantage of the stronger is really what the stronger merely believes to be an advantage. (340b) At this point in the dialogue, Cleitophon’s suggestion has given Thrasymachus the option of choosing to adopt a legalist position whereby justice is defined as obeying the laws, or the position more conducive to the immoralist one whereby justice is defined as what is in the interest of the stronger. If Thrasymachus had adopted Cleitophon’s suggestion, then he would be advocating the legalist view that justice is obedience to the laws and a commentator such as G. F. Hourani would have a clear case for his position.(21) This is so because the tyrant in a society would be laying down laws regardless of whether they would be truly in the interest, or merely seem to be in the interest of the tyrant. In either case, justice would be defined legalistically as an obedience to the given laws of the tyrant at a given time and place.

However, Thrasymachus specifically denies Cleitophon’s suggestion and thereby denies the legalist position in favor of defining justice as the interest of the stronger. (340c) What this means is that a distinction between the concepts of the "tyrant" (qua ruler) and the "stronger" is made explicit. In Cleitophon’s view, the tyrant enacts laws that would be just for the many to obey whether they were in the interest of the tyrant or not. If this were the case then justice would be defined as the ruled many obeying the laws of the tyrant. But Thrasymachus is interested in the tyrant only insofar as such an individual is understood as the stronger. (343c) Thrasymachus assumes that the strongest person will become the tyrant and when such a tyrant enacts laws for the many to follow, these laws are enacted with an eye to the many’s exploitation. In this way, justice is the interest of the stronger, tyrant who happens to be the ruler of the society.

Thrasymachus’ rejection of Cleitophon’s suggestion commits him to a position of immoralism and draws out the distinction between the conceptions of the tyrant and the stronger. Thrasymachus’ commitment to this immoralism also saddles him with the charge of being inconsistent when proffering a definition of justice. Both Thrasymachus’ immoralism and the inconsistency in Thrasymachus’ position concerning the status of the tyrant as living the life of injustice give credence to my claim that there is this third type of individual in society, distinct from the tyrant and the many—namely, the stronger. When we consider the definition of justice and injustice form the standpoint of the stronger, Thrasymachus’ three statements actually remain consistent. The unjust life of the kreitton entails violating the laws of the ruler at all costs since the concern and advantage would be for the stronger’s own self-interest.

Once the stronger individual is recognized as a part of Thrasymachus’ schematization, then it is possible to see how, from the standpoint of the stronger, the three statements that Thrasymachus makes regarding justice and its opposite remain consistent. Unfortunately, the problem of envisioning the same situation as being both just and unjust at the same time from the points of view of the many and the tyrant remains. When taking Thrasymachus’ three statements regarding justice and injustice in their entirety, it seems to follow that if justice is what is advantageous for the tyrant, then injustice, as its opposite, would be disadvantageous for the tyrant. However, if we take what Thrasymachus is saying regarding justice and injustice as applicable to the stronger, the inconsistency issue is skirted. This is to say that from the standpoint of the stronger, what is unjust would be disadvantageous both for the many as well as for the tyrant. The "other" which was the cause of inconsistency and concern for Kerferd and Annas can be either the ruled or the ruler or both. It makes no difference as both the ruled and the ruler are exploited by the kreitton. The many follow laws and are exploited by the tyrant. The stronger individual realizes this and does what is unjust, in terms either of breaking the laws or of exploiting the many. So, in this sense, the stronger individual, if he or she can get away with it, always seeks to exploit the exploited as well as exploit the exploiter.

V.

What I have attempted to do in this paper is to draw out of Thrasymachus’ account a genesis of the tyrant from the many in a society. A tyrant just does not come out of nowhere and rule over a group of people. I believe that, in his conversation with Socrates and Cleitophon, Thrasymachus is offering us a developmental account of how the stronger individual detaches from the many to rise to the ranks of tyranthood by leading a life of injustice. At the same time, this life of injustice must be buffered, I believe, by a seeming or an appearance of justice whereby the stronger individual can dupe both the tyrant and the many in the ascent to tyranthood. I have tried to argue for this double life of justice and injustice through the support of Thrasymachus’ own words coupled with the suggestions of Glaucon in Republic II and Professor Henderson’s account of Setarcos.

I have also tried to show how the inconsistency issue can be skirted if we take Thrasymachus’ three statements regarding justice from the standpoint of the stronger. Both the ruler and the ruled become exploited by the kreitton. The task, then, for the stronger individual becomes devising ways in which to always get away with the exploitation. For it seems possible that the many and the tyrant, if confronted with the stronger’s activities, would not allow themselves to be exploited. Thrasymachus suggests that stealth be used by the perfectly unjust tyrant who possesses unlimited strength. (344a) But this stealth seems to be an option also for the stronger individual in the exploiting process. Stealth offers the path of least resistance as was pointed out in Henderson’s example of Setarcos. Furtive and covert unjust activity masked by outward signs of justice and integrity would enable the stronger individual to get away with exploiting the exploited and the exploiter. I have suggested that seeming or appearing to be just in the public realm while privately pursuing injustice would be conducive to this stealth that is endorsed by Thrasymachus. Thus, the double life of justice and injustice that the stronger individual leads.

Leading the stronger’s life of pleonexia, whereby an individual seeks to overpower and dupe another for the purpose of personal advantage and happiness is possible—certainly, Henderson's Setarcos and Thrasymachus think so. But such a life would entail an individual’s leading double roles. One would find it necessary to put up a deceptive front or an "appearance" of leading a life of justice so as to have the freedom to pursue what is entailed in the unjust life. Such a double-rolled life can be applied both to the "stronger," imperfectly unjust individual who seeks tyranthood and to the "strongest," perfectly unjust tyrant as in Henderson’s example of Setarcos.

http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciArp.htm
Back to top Go down
https://dissidentsphilosophy.forumotion.com
Unreasonable
Animated Voice
Animated Voice
Unreasonable


Male
Number of posts : 728
Age : 41
Location : Purgatory
Registration date : 2008-12-13

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeTue Jan 20, 2009 10:02 am

That is a lot of thought to get through Fool. Let me take a stab at it.

First of all, I think that Thrasymachus is mainly arguing from a point of superiority & inferiority through strength of arms (or force, or even reason). However, strength and justice are two very separate things in my eyes. A man can be strong, but that does not make him just. A man can be just, but that does not make him strong. To become both just and strong is something that Socrates exposes to the audience throughout the discourse of The Repulik. Furthermore, I believe that Thrasymachus is not so much concerned about justice or injustice themselves, as concepts, because what he seems to argue is on the behalf of strength in-and-of-itself. He basically says: the winner is the winner. Well, yes, the winner is the winner after all, but this does not explain nor describe to us what Justice actually-is.

That is where I see the conversation that Thrasymachus has with Socrates ends, and Socrates goes on to explain Justice more in-depth.

The assertion that the ruler or tyrant is both Just & Unjust seems superfluous to me. He cannot be both at the same time. The reason for this is the contradictory-affect of Injustice. If the tyrant ever practices Injustice, at all, then the legions that he commands can turn on him for exposing his weakness (that he contradicts his own ideals). This is basic hypocrisy. I say that I love Afrikan boys & girls, and then right after I say it, I go and drop some bombs on some Afrikan homes just because I'm bored with myself and want to watch some Afrikan bodies twist and writhe while being burnt alive. This is incongruous to Justice. In other words, it both does not and cannot make sense, in any form, at all. How could it? How could the tyrant be actually-just and unjust???

Here is the conclusion that I am heading toward: Injustice is the reality; Justice is the actuality.

Injustice seems commonplace, because we are selfish animals. However, where do people or persons become supposedly-"selfless". That is what needs to be investigated. And people buy into an Ideal, a Social Contract. This is the Just thing! It is not a tyrant; it is an ideology! If somebody signs this contract, and then breaks it, then nobody owes anything to him any longer. Because if a man does not have his word, at least, then what does he have? If he is a hypocrite, then who will trust him? Furthermore, if such a man were in charge of the legions, then would the soldiers accept a master who is willing to betray their lives at the drop of a hat???

Or, do people only accept and trust leaders that they ***FEEL*** they can depend on???
Back to top Go down
The Fool
Administrator
The Fool


Male
Number of posts : 368
Age : 37
Location : United States Midwest
Registration date : 2008-12-12

Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitimeFri Jan 23, 2009 10:47 am

Quote :
First of all, I think that Thrasymachus is mainly arguing from a point of superiority & inferiority through strength of arms (or force, or even reason).


Yes.

Quote :
However, strength and justice are two very separate things in my eyes.

Not really. It is the person with power and influence within a society that controls the justice system.

The justice system is merely a monopoly or appendage of those with power and influence.

( Much like a centralized government is.)

Quote :
A man can be strong, but that does not make him just.

That doesn't matter.

A man can pretend to be just in order to control others in getting what they want. ( Power.)

( Even when under the pretend image of justice that they put up for themelves they are unjust.)

I'll use a analogy of a master and their slave:

A slave ends up being beaten by someone in the middle of a town market. The master of the slave ends up going to the justice department seeking punishment on the individual responsible for beating his slave not because he has any real emotional or personal concern for his beaten slave since such a person is merely a tool to him but because his slave is a viable economical producer or investment amongst his place of business which he benefits from in having the slave as a apart of his individual property ( A slave is not useful and profitable if it is maimed, injured, or blinded.) however since we live in a society that likes to make illusional images appear more real than they actually are the master along with the justice system that he influences will put on a real effective public relations appearance in which they will feign that they are seeking justice on behalf of the slave by pretending that they have a emotional concern for them even when they don't.

It becomes necessary for those with power to put up this pretend image that they care about those which they rule in that such a fake false appearance that they come to create is the very thing that gives them the support from the people they command in the first place in electing themselves to positions of influence.

( Prey upon people's weaknesses.)

When the master utilizes the justice system for this purpose they also send a powerful message as well: For all those would be future offenders who mess with my private property ( In this case public slaves and servants) I'll come after you through the justice system which I monopolize.

The illusion of all of this is that the justice system puts off the facade that it serves the interests of all people equally but in reality it serves only the interests of those with power in that beyond those of power everybody else is under control or mere pawns however since such pawns are the producers of economical profit for those in positions of power it becomes necessary to protect them from any uncontrolled rebel forces within society all the while putting up the pretend image of emotional concern for them as well in that such pretend images makes it easier to control the populance especially if they come to think of their leaders as sympathetic benevolent people who truely have a genuine concern for their existential well being.

So in a sense the justice system exists solely for those of power by protecting their property.

( Everyone who does not have power is the property of someone with power.)

( If you work for Mcdonalds you are the property and investment of Mcdonalds as an employee. Ect,Ect.)

( Ironically all of this is happening simultaneously where society puts up the illusion that everybody is somehow free.)





Does this analogy make sense? Or is this a poor analogy on my behalf?

Quote :
Injustice seems commonplace, because we are selfish animals.


Yes.


Quote :
However, where do people or persons become supposedly-"selfless".

Nowhere.

Quote :
Or, do people only accept and trust leaders that they ***FEEL*** they can depend on??

Bullshit sells. Think about it for a moment.

[/quote]
Back to top Go down
https://dissidentsphilosophy.forumotion.com
Sponsored content





Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. Empty
PostSubject: Re: Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.   Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power. I_icon_minitime

Back to top Go down
 
Justice And Law Only Benefits Those With Power.
Back to top 
Page 1 of 1
 Similar topics
-
» Power
» The Collapse of Amerikan Power
» AND HEALING ALL UNDER THE POWER OF THE DEVIL
» Panthepsychic Comics #3 END Part Two: AND HEALING ALL UNDER THE POWER OF THE DEVIL!
» The Power Of The Lucid Dreamer (Mind-Bending, Cosmic Christianity!)

Permissions in this forum:You cannot reply to topics in this forum
Dissidents Philosophy Forum :: Philosophy-
Jump to: